Fixed Points, Part 4: Stability
A fixed point of a function is an input the function maps to itself. When we study the fixed points of a function, we can learn many interesting things about the function itself. This last of four parts talks about the stability of fixed points.
Classifying fixed points
- Gaiane
- You said that attraction basins are more interesting in their ability to describe their fixed point.
- Plautus
- Yes.
- Gaiane
- What do you mean?
- Plautus
- I don’t know about you, but when I hear about a mathematical object, my first instinct is to classify it.
- Gaiane
- You want to classify fixed points?
- Plautus
- Sure. We already know a bit…
Given a function f : X → X
, its set of fixed points is X
modulo attraction in f
. We’ll write Fixed(f)
for the set of fixed points of f
.
- Gaiane
- What do you mean by attraction in
f
? - Plautus
- I had this definition for
x
andy
attracting iffᵃ x = fᵇ y
. I’m saying attraction inf
to make the dependence onf
clear. - Gaiane
- Oh, ok. Go on.
One important class of fixed points is the set of fixed points of a certain degree. We’ll write Fixedⁿ(f)
for these.
- Gaiane
- Right, but these aren’t all of them.
- Plautus
- Yep.
- Gaiane
- Like the fixed point of the successor function on natural numbers.
- Plautus
- Well, that’s actually just because we’re not considering enough numbers.
- Gaiane
- What?!
Define ω+1
to be the set of natural numbers, together with a new element we call ω
. We then extend the definition of behavior to allow transfinite induction on the length of the chain. Then we find that the successor function, extended to have the value ω
on input ω
, has as a degree-1 fixed point at ω
.
- Gaiane
- What just happened?
- Plautus
- Uhh… I’m not sure.
- Gaiane
- So you didn’t follow that?
- Plautus
- No. I don’t know where those words came from, either. It wasn’t me.
- Gaiane
- What I got out of it is that the successor function secretly has a degree-1 fixed point.
- Plautus
- I think it had something to do with the successor function always increasing its input by a fixed amount.
- Gaiane
- Oh, maybe all fixed points are fixed-degree fixed points? (Some secretly?)
- Plautus
- “All types” is a bit intimidating. Let’s start with very simple domains.
Fixed points on finite domains
Let X
have exactly n
elements, and let f
be an arbitrary function X → X
. We claim that any fixed point of f
has finite degree.
- Gaiane
- Why’s this true?
- Plautus
- I’m not sure, but my intuition tells me that on a finite domain, all
f
can do is swap some elements around. - Gaiane
- Well, it can also map some elements to other elements.
- Plautus
- Actually, we can eliminate that.
First, we turn f
into a permutation, by inventing X’
, which is X
but equating elements x
and y
if f x = f y
. Then we have an f’ : X’ → X’
, because f
is well-defined on equivalence classes in X’
. Furthermore, f’
is a permutation since it maps distinct inputs to distinct outputs by definition.
- Gaiane
- Ah, but a fixed behavior of
f
has degreen
when all the points it cycles through are fixed points offⁿ
. - Plautus
- And if
f
is a permutation onX’
…
Now, we can see the set of permutations on X’
as a group, and since X’
is finite, this group is also finite. Thus it has finite order. So there is some k
such that (f’)ᵏ
is the identity of which all points have degree 1.
- Gaiane
- Not really how I thought of putting it, but sure.
- Plautus
- What would you do?
- Gaiane
- I’d just construct the order explicitly.
Since X
had exactly n
elements, X’
has at most n
elements. So there are at most n!
permutations on it. So (f’)^(n!)
must be the identity. Thus f
has a degree dividing n!
.
- Plautus
- Ok. In any case, it has fixed degree.
- Gaiane
- Well, we should move on to the natural numbers next. They’re the simplest infinite set.
Fixed behaviors in the integers
- Plautus
- I’m still a bit confused about the whole “fixed behavior of the successor function” business.
- Gaiane
- How about we ignore that for now, and characterize fixed points as “fixed degree or increase arbitrarily”.
- Plautus
- Are those the only two options?
- Gaiane
- I think so.
A function f : ℕ → ℕ
diverges on an input x
if fⁿ(x)
can be arbitrarily large (for arbitrarily large x
).
- Plautus
- What do you mean, can be arbitrarily large?
- Gaiane
- The formal definition is a
lim sup
; basically, for any threshold valueT
, there’s somen
so thatfⁿ(x) > T
. - Plautus
- Ok. Is there a difference between that and
lim inf
, where there’s somen
such thatfⁿ⁺ᵏ(x) > T
for allk
? - Gaiane
- No, consider
If lim sup fⁿ(x) → ∞
, then lim inf fⁿ(x) → ∞
. For suppose not, and instead lim inf fⁿ(x) = T
. Then for any n
, there is a larger m
such that fᵐ(x) ≤ T
.
Let’s write out a sequence of such m
. First we have the m
for n = 0
, which we’ll call m₀
. Then we have the m
for n = m₀ + 1
, which we’ll call m₁
(note that m₁ > m₀
). Next, we have the m
for n = m₁ + 1
, which we call m₂
and for which m₂ > m₁ > m₀
. Continuing in this manner, we find a
m₀ < m₁ < m₂ < m₃ < ...
We can write (f^mᵢ)(x)
as aᵢ
, so we have a sequence
a₀ , a₁ , a₂ , a₃ , ...
which are all less than T
.
But since there are a finite number of elements less than T
, some of the aᵢ
terms must have the same value. And if aᵢ = aⱼ
, then (f^mᵢ)(x) = (f^mⱼ)(x)
, so (f^(mᵢ + k))(x) = (f^(mⱼ + k))(x)
, so that f
has degree mⱼ - mᵢ
.
But then fⁿ(x)
takes on only finitely many values (at most mᵢ + (mⱼ - mᵢ) = mⱼ
), and thus we cannot have lim sup fⁿ(x) → ∞
. This is a contradiction.
- Plautus
- You thought of all that?
- Gaiane
- The proof really obscures the intuition here.
Basically, the point is that if fⁿ(x)
has arbitrarily large terms, it can’t have finite degree because then it would only take on finitely many values (which would thus not be arbitrarily large).
But then fⁿ(x)
can never repeat terms (once it repeats a term, it is stuck in a cycle, since every term is decided only by the previous term). And if fⁿ(x)
can not repeat terms, it eventually “uses up” all of the small ones.
- Plautus
- That makes a bit more sense now.
- Gaiane
- Also, the proof shows that if function does not diverge, must have a fixed degree and vice versa.
- Plautus
- How?
- Gaiane
- By the same intuition…
In general, if a function does not diverge, then lim sup fⁿ(x) = T
. Then after at most T
terms, fⁿ(x)
must repeat an output, and so begins a cycle. So fⁿ
has degree at most T
.
On the other hand, if f
has a fixed degree, it cannot diverge since it only cycles through a finite set of values.
- Plautus
- Wait, so you’ve proven the theorem we wanted: either a function diverges, or it has a fixed degree.
- Gaiane
- Looks like I did!
- Plautus
- I notice that your proof made use of a reasoning by contradiction. What about the same theorem in constructive logic?
- Gaiane
- I don’t know. I’m not too familiar with constructive logic, but it’d be interesting to formulate this theorem in Coq.
- Plautus
- Not to me. Anyway, so it sounds like we’ve got functions on the naturals all figured out.
- Gaiane
- I wouldn’t say that. Here’s an open problem a friend told me about.
Consider the function
f(n) = if (even? n) then (n / 2) else (3 * n + 1)
Clearly it has a fixed point at 0
of degree 1, and it also has a fixed-point of degree 3, which is 1 : 4 : 2 : 1 : ...
. Are there any other fixed points?
- Gaiane
- Apparently this is a very hard problem, to the point that Paul Erdős said, “Mathematics is not yet ripe for such problems.”
- Plautus
- Huh. Weird. So it might have another fixed point of some large degree somewhere, or it might diverge.
- Gaiane
- Yeah. Mathematicians have even proven bounds on the degree; it can’t be smaller than 136, for example.
- Plautus
- Weird!
- Gaiane
- The point is, though we know all functions on the naturals diverge or have finite-degree fixed points, we don’t necessarily know which fixed points are which.
- Plautus
- Still, that’s cool. We should move on to continuous spaces next, right?
- Gaiane
- Maybe some other time. It’s late, and I ought to go to sleep. See you again soon.